Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis

Abstract Background AIDS, SARS, and the recent epidemics of the avian-flu have all served to remind us the debate over the limits of the moral duty to care. It is important to first consider the question of whether or not the "duty to treat" might be subject to contextual constraints. The...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Civaner, Murat, Arda, Berna
Format: Article in Journal/Newspaper
Language:English
Published: BioMed Central Ltd. 2008
Subjects:
Online Access:http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2334/8/29
id ftbiomed:oai:biomedcentral.com:1471-2334-8-29
record_format openpolar
spelling ftbiomed:oai:biomedcentral.com:1471-2334-8-29 2023-05-15T15:34:37+02:00 Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis Civaner, Murat Arda, Berna 2008-03-06 http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2334/8/29 en eng BioMed Central Ltd. http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2334/8/29 Copyright 2008 Civaner and Arda; licensee BioMed Central Ltd. Research article 2008 ftbiomed 2008-04-25T23:11:10Z Abstract Background AIDS, SARS, and the recent epidemics of the avian-flu have all served to remind us the debate over the limits of the moral duty to care. It is important to first consider the question of whether or not the "duty to treat" might be subject to contextual constraints. The purpose of this study was to investigate the opinions and beliefs held by both physicians and dentists regarding the occupational risks of infectious diseases, and to analyze the argument that the notion of "presumed consent" on the part of professionals may be grounds for supporting the duty to treat. Methods For this cross-sectional survey, the study population was selected from among physicians and dentists in Ankara. All of the 373 participants were given a self-administered questionnaire. Results In total, 79.6% of the participants said that they either had some degree of knowledge about the risks when they chose their profession or that they learned of the risks later during their education and training. Of the participants, 5.2% said that they would not have chosen this profession if they had been informed of the risks. It was found that 57% of the participants believed that there is a standard level of risk, and 52% of the participants stated that certain diseases would exceed the level of acceptable risk unless specific protective measures were implemented. Conclusion If we use the presumed consent argument to establish the duty of the HCW to provide care, we are confronted with problems ranging over the difficulty of choosing a profession autonomously, the constant level of uncertainty present in the medical profession, the near-impossibility of being able to evaluate retrospectively whether every individual was informed, and the seemingly inescapable problem that this practice would legitimize, and perhaps even foster, discrimination against patients with certain diseases. Our findings suggest that another problem can be added to the list: one-fifth of the participants in this study either lacked adequate knowledge of the occupational risks when they chose the medical profession or were not sufficiently informed of these risks during their faculty education and training. Furthermore, in terms of the moral duty to provide care, it seems that most HCWs are more concerned about the availability of protective measures than about whether they had been informed of a particular risk beforehand. For all these reasons, the presumed consent argument is not persuasive enough, and cannot be used to justify the duty to provide care. It is therefore more useful to emphasize justifications other than presumed consent when defining the duty of HCWs to provide care, such as the social contract between society and the medical profession and the fact that HCWs have a greater ability to provide medical aid. Article in Journal/Newspaper Avian flu BioMed Central
institution Open Polar
collection BioMed Central
op_collection_id ftbiomed
language English
description Abstract Background AIDS, SARS, and the recent epidemics of the avian-flu have all served to remind us the debate over the limits of the moral duty to care. It is important to first consider the question of whether or not the "duty to treat" might be subject to contextual constraints. The purpose of this study was to investigate the opinions and beliefs held by both physicians and dentists regarding the occupational risks of infectious diseases, and to analyze the argument that the notion of "presumed consent" on the part of professionals may be grounds for supporting the duty to treat. Methods For this cross-sectional survey, the study population was selected from among physicians and dentists in Ankara. All of the 373 participants were given a self-administered questionnaire. Results In total, 79.6% of the participants said that they either had some degree of knowledge about the risks when they chose their profession or that they learned of the risks later during their education and training. Of the participants, 5.2% said that they would not have chosen this profession if they had been informed of the risks. It was found that 57% of the participants believed that there is a standard level of risk, and 52% of the participants stated that certain diseases would exceed the level of acceptable risk unless specific protective measures were implemented. Conclusion If we use the presumed consent argument to establish the duty of the HCW to provide care, we are confronted with problems ranging over the difficulty of choosing a profession autonomously, the constant level of uncertainty present in the medical profession, the near-impossibility of being able to evaluate retrospectively whether every individual was informed, and the seemingly inescapable problem that this practice would legitimize, and perhaps even foster, discrimination against patients with certain diseases. Our findings suggest that another problem can be added to the list: one-fifth of the participants in this study either lacked adequate knowledge of the occupational risks when they chose the medical profession or were not sufficiently informed of these risks during their faculty education and training. Furthermore, in terms of the moral duty to provide care, it seems that most HCWs are more concerned about the availability of protective measures than about whether they had been informed of a particular risk beforehand. For all these reasons, the presumed consent argument is not persuasive enough, and cannot be used to justify the duty to provide care. It is therefore more useful to emphasize justifications other than presumed consent when defining the duty of HCWs to provide care, such as the social contract between society and the medical profession and the fact that HCWs have a greater ability to provide medical aid.
format Article in Journal/Newspaper
author Civaner, Murat
Arda, Berna
spellingShingle Civaner, Murat
Arda, Berna
Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis
author_facet Civaner, Murat
Arda, Berna
author_sort Civaner, Murat
title Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis
title_short Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis
title_full Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis
title_fullStr Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis
title_full_unstemmed Can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? An analysis
title_sort can "presumed consent" justify the duty to treat infectious diseases? an analysis
publisher BioMed Central Ltd.
publishDate 2008
url http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2334/8/29
genre Avian flu
genre_facet Avian flu
op_relation http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2334/8/29
op_rights Copyright 2008 Civaner and Arda; licensee BioMed Central Ltd.
_version_ 1766364948404895744